More Reading
Timeless
Surely nothing is possible without time? But according
to physicist Julian Barbour, it doesn't even exist
TIME seems to be the most powerful force,
an irresistible river carrying us from birth to death. To
most people it is an inescapable part of life, a fundamental
element of the Universe.
But I think that time is an illusion. Physicists
struggling to unify quantum mechanics and Einstein's general
theory of relativity have found hints that the Universe is
timeless. I believe that this idea should be taken seriously.
Paradoxically, we might be able to explain the mysterious
"arrow of time"—the difference between past and future—by
abandoning time. But to understand how, we need to change
radically our ideas of how the Universe works.
Let's start with Newton's picture of absolute time. He argued
that objects exist in an immense immobile space, stretching
like a block of glass from infinity to infinity. His time
is an invisible river that "flows equably without relation
to anything external". Newton's absolute space and time form
a framework that exists at a deeper level than the objects
in it.
To see how it works, imagine a universe containing only three
particles. To describe its history in Newton's terms, you
specify a succession of sets of 10 numbers: one for time and
three for the spatial coordinates of each of the three particles.
But this picture is suspect. As space-time framework is invisible,
how can you determine all the numbers? As far back as 1872,
the Austrian physicist Ernst Mach argued that the Universe
should be described solely in terms of observable things,
the separations between its objects.
With that in mind, we can use a very different framework for
the three-particle Universe—a strange, abstract realm called
Triangle Land. Think of the three particles as the corners
of a triangle. This triangle is completely defined by the
lengths of its three sides—just three numbers. You can take
these three numbers and use them as coordinates, to mark a
point in an abstract "configuration space".
Each possible arrangement of three particles corresponds to
a point in this space. There are geometrical restrictions—no triangle has one side longer than the other two put together—so it turns out that all the points lie in or on a pyramid.
At the apex of Triangle land, where all three coordinates
are zero, is a point that I call Alpha. It represents the
triangle that has sides all of zero length (in other words,
all three particles are in the same place).
In the same way, the configurations of a four-particle universe
form Tetrahedron Land. It has six dimensions, corresponding
to the six separations between pairs of particles—hard to
conceive, but it exists as a mathematical entity. And even
for the stupendous number of particles that make up our own
Universe, we can envisage a vast multidimensional structure
representing its configurations. In collaboration with Bruno Bertotti of Pavia University in Italy, I have shown that conventional
physics still works in this stranger world. As Plato taught
that reality exists as perfect forms, I think of the patterns
of particles as Platonic forms, and call their totality
Platonia.
Platonia is an image of eternity. It is all the arrangements
of matter that can be. Looking at it as a whole, there seems
to be no more river of time. But could time be hiding? Perhaps
there is some sort of local time that makes sense to inhabitants
of Platonia.
In classical physics, something like time can indeed creep
back in. If you were to lay out all the instants of an evolving
Newtonian universe, it would look like a path drawn in Platonia.
As a godlike being, outside Platonia, you could run your finger
along the path, touching points that correspond to each different
arrangement of matter, and see a universe that continuously
changes from one state to another. Any point on this path
still has something that looks like a definite past and future.
Now's the place
But we know that classical physics is wrong. The world is
described by quantum mechanics—and in the arena of Platonia,
quantum mechanics kills time.
In the quantum wave theory created by Schrodinger, a particle
has no definite position, instead it has a fuzzy probability
of being at each possible position. And for three particles,
say, there is a certain probability of their forming a triangle
in a particular orientation with its centre of mass at some
absolute position. The deepest quantum mysteries arise because
of holistic statements of this kind. The probabilities are
for the whole, not the parts.
What probabilities could quantum mechanics specify for the
complete Universe that has Platonia as its arena? There cannot
be probabilities at different times because Platonia itself
is timeless. There can only be once-and-for-all probabilities
for each possible configuration.
In this picture, there are no definite paths. We are not beings
progressing from one instant to another. Rather, there are
many "Nows" in which a version of us exists—not in any past
or future, but scattered in our region of Platonia.
This may sound like the "many worlds" interpretation of quantum
mechanics, published in 1957 by Hugh Everett of Princeton
University. But in that scheme time still exists: history
is a path that branches whenever some quantum decision has
to be made. In my picture there are no paths. Each point of
Platonia has a probability, and that's the end of the story.
A similar position was reached by much more sophisticated
arguments more than 30 years ago. Americans Bryce Dewitt and
John Wheeler combined quantum mechanics and Einstein's theory
of general relativity to produce an equation that describes
the whole Universe. Put into the equation a configuration
of the Universe, and out comes a probability for that configuration.
There is no mention of time. Admittedly, the Wheeler-Dewitt
equation is controversial and fraught with mathematical difficulties,
but if quantum cosmology is anything like it—if it is about
probabilities—the timeless picture is plausible.
So let's take seriously the idea of a "probability
mist" that
covers the timeless Platonic landscape. The density of the
mist is just the relative probability of the corresponding
configuration being realised, or experienced, as an instantaneous
state of the Universe—as a Now. If some Nows in Platonia
have much higher probabilities than others, they are the ones
that are actually experienced. This is like ordinary statistical
physics: a glass of water could boil spontaneously, but the
probability is so low that we never see it happen.
All this seems a far cry from the reality of our lives. Where
is the history we read about? Where are our memories? Where
is the bustling, changing world of our experience? Those configurations
of the Universe for which the probability mist has a high
density, and so are liked to be experienced, must have within
them an appearance of history—a set of mutually consistent
records that suggests we have a past. I call these configurations
"time capsules"
Present past
An arbitrary matter distribution, like dots distributed at
random, will not have any meaning. It will not tell a story.
Almost all imaginable matter distributions are of this kind;
only the tiniest fraction seem to carry meaningful information.
One of the most remarkable facts about our Universe is that
it does have a meaningful structure. All the matter we can
observe in any way is found to contain records of a past.
The first scientists to realise this were geologists. Examining
the structure of rocks and fossils, they constructed a long
history of the Earth. Modern cosmology has extended this to
a history of the Universe right back to the big bang.
What is more, we are somehow directly aware of the passing
of time, and we see motion—a change of position over time.
You may feel these are such powerful sensations that any attempt
to deny them is ridiculous. But imagine yourself frozen in
time. You are simply a static arrangement of matter, yet all
your memories and experience are still there, represented
by physical patterns within your brain—probably as the strengths
of the synapse connections between neurons. Just as the structure
of geological strata and fossils seem to be evidence of a
past, our brains contain physical structures consistent with
the appearance of recent and distant events. These structures
could surely lead to the impression of time passing.
Even the direct perception of motion could arise through the
presence in the brain of information about several different
positions of the objects we see in motion.
And that is the essence of my proposal. There is no history
laid out along a path, there are only records contained within
Nows. This timeless vision may seem perverse. But it turns
out to have one great potential strength: it could explain
the arrow of time.
We are so accustomed to history that we forget how peculiar
it is. According to conventional cosmology, our Universe must
have started out in an extraordinarily special state to give
rise to the highly ordered Universe we find around us, with
its arrow of time and records of a past. All matter and energy
must have originated at a single point, and had an almost
perfectly uniform distribution immediately after the big bang.
Hitherto, the only explanation that science has provided is
the anthropic argument: we experience configurations of the
Universe that seem to have a history because only these configurations
have the characteristics to produce beings who can experience
anything. I believe that timeless quantum cosmology provides
a far more satisfying explanation.
In Platonia, there are no initial conditions. Only two factors
determine where the probability mist is dense: the form of
some equation (like the Wheeler-DeWitt equation) and the shape
of Platonia. And by sheer logical necessity, Platonia is profoundly
asymmetric. Like Triangle Land, it is a lopsided continent
with a special point Alpha corresponding to the configuration
in which every particle is at the same place.
From this singular point, the timeless landscape opens out,
flower-like, to points that represent configurations of the
Universe of arbitrary size and complexity. My conjecture is
that the shape of Platonia cannot fail to influence the distribution
of the quantum probability mist. It could funnel the mist
onto time capsules, those meaningful arrangements that seem
to contain records of a past that began at Alpha.
This is, of course, only speculation, but quantum mechanics
supports it. In 1929, the British physicist Nevill Mott and
Werner Heisenberg from Germany explained how alpha particles,
emitted by radioactive nuclei, form straight tracks in cloud
chambers. Mott pointed out that, quantum mechanically, the
emitted alpha particle is a spherical wave which slowly leaks
out of the nucleus. "It is difficult to picture how it is
that an outgoing spherical wave can produce a straight line,"he
argued. We think intuitively that it should ionise atoms at
random throughout space.
Mott noted that we think this way because we imagine that
quantum processes take place in ordinary three-dimensional
space. In fact, the possible configurations of the alpha particle
and the particles in the detecting chamber must be regarded
as the points of a hugely multidimensional configuration space,
a miniature Platonia, with the position of the radioactive
nucleus playing the role of Alpha.
Ageless creation
When Mott viewed the chamber from this perspective, his equations
predicted the existence of the tracks. The basic fact that
quantum mechanics treats configurations as whole entities
leads to track formation. And a track is just a point in configuration
space—but one that creates the appearance of a past, just
like our own memories.
There is one more reason to embrace the timeless view. Many
theoretical physicists now recognise that the usual notions
of time and space must break down near the big bang. They
find themselves forced to seek a timeless description of the
"beginning" of the Universe, even though they use
time elsewhere. It seems more consistent and economical to
use an entirely timeless description.
But for these ideas to be more than speculation, they should
have concrete, measurable results. Fortunately, Stephen Hawking
and other theorists have shown that the Wheeler-DeWitt equation
can lead to verifiable predictions. For example, established
physical theories cannot predict a value for the cosmological
constant, which measures the gravitational repulsion of empty
space. But calculations based on the Wheeler-DeWitt equation
suggest that it should have a very small value. It should
soon be possible to measure the cosmological constant, either
by taking the brightness of far-off supernovae and using that
to track the expansion of the Universe, or by analysing the
shape of humps and bumps in the cosmic microwave background.
And a definitive equation of quantum cosmology should give
us a precise prediction for the value of the constant. It
is a distant prospect, but the nonexistence of time could
be confirmed by experiment.
The notion of time as an invisible framework that contains
and constrains the Universe is not unlike the crystal spheres
invented centuries ago to carry the planets. After the spheres
had been shattered by Tycho Brahe's observations, Kepler said:
"We must philosophise about these things differently." Much
of modern physics stems from this insight. We need a new notion
of time.
TOP
|